Trust is not enoughThis essay considers trust and distrust, and in particular whether
distrusting a person or an organization is enough to discredit its statements or
evidence. I will show that contrary to what is often assumed by JFK researchers,
simple distrust is not enough.
Increasingly, conspiracists are using past omissions and errors by the FBI,
the Secret Service, and other governmental agencies—which in principle are not
to be denied unless one believes in a perfect world—to justify distrusting
them completely and then rejecting whichever of their statements and evidence
are convenient at the moment. They offer statements such as:
Perhaps the ultimate expression of this view is the statement of one critic
that nearly the entire credibility of the Warren Commission Report stands or
falls on whether we can trust the evidence provided them by the FBI. Naturally,
this critic soundly rejects the report.
Let us examine the general argument underlying the mindset of
distrustfulness. It can be expressed in four steps:
This argument is triply fallacious and must be rejected. First, even if we
grant that the premise in Step 1 is accurate for the JFK case (which is seldom
demonstrated), the conclusion in Step 2, that the government may lie again, is
fallacious because it is based on the invalid principle of induction—that a
conclusion from one instance can be applied to another. (The correct version of
Step 2 would be that we cannot know whether the government will lie again.) This
then invalidates the conclusion in Step 3, that we can’t trust the government
in specific instances—the second fallacy. (The corrected Step 3 would state
that we cannot know whether to trust the government’s assertions and
evidence.) The next problem stems from the fact that between Steps 3 and 4, two
major points are missing, namely that ways for testing and validating evidence
exist, and that the government itself has built into its system of evaluating
evidence multiple safeguards such as chains of custody, testifying under oath,
and using forensic procedures to check evidence. This invalidates the conclusion
in Step 4, that we must reject all evidence from the government—the third
fallacy. (Step 4 should state that we cannot know whether we should reject any
or all evidence from the government or from any other source.) On balance, we
might call this overall argument "The three fallacies of doubt."
Doubters and critics can also fool themselves into thinking that they are
being more careful with evidence than the government is, when in reality they
are doing the opposite. They ignore the fact that through its legal system, the
government inserts these safeguards between the distrust embodied in Step 3 and
the rejection in Step 4. In effect, the government is telling us not to trust
its own institutions if we can’t validate their evidence. It is thus
subjecting itself to a rigorous and objective test, whereas the critics are
settling for the hasty conclusion of dismissing the statements and evidence out
of hand. Furthermore, the government is being harsher on itself than on
others—whereas it commonly applies the standard of "Trust but
verify" to international treaties, concerning itself it admonishes,
"Don’t trust us until you verify us." By contrast, critics say to
the government, "We knee-jerk distrust you and so don’t need to verify
you." If their own government will go the extra mile and recognize that
trust is not enough, shouldn’t the critics?
The logically sound attitude toward the government (or any other agency or
person, for that matter) can be expressed formally in three chains of logic,
each of which applies to a different hypothetical situation:
In other words, no matter whether the government has never lied, has
sometimes lied, or has always lied, we can say nothing with certainty about
whether it will lie in the future. When the critics conclude that because the
government has lied in the past, it will always lie in the future, they are
using a fallacious modification of the second logical train above, saying in
effect, "You lied once, you will lie ever after." This is far stronger
than even the common "Once a liar, always a liar." Such unjustified
negativism violates both classical logic and established American legal practice
(where a witness’s previous lies cannot be used to discredit his present
testimony).
How then should we handle the question of trust? The solution is
easy—forget about the track record of the source and evaluate its evidence and
assertions individually and with an open mind. Trust nobody, and check them all
equally. I am puzzled why so few JFK researchers take that next step and try to
check the government’s individual statements and evidence. Since the
government itself tells us we should do this, why do the critics refuse? I come
up with only four possible reasons, none of which please me:
"Pleasing" notwithstanding, I believe that all four of these reasons apply to today’s critical community. Specific examples will be presented in another essay.